Jump to content

Wikipedia:Reference desk/Mathematics

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Welcome to the mathematics section
of the Wikipedia reference desk.
Select a section:
Want a faster answer?

Main page: Help searching Wikipedia

   

How can I get my question answered?

  • Select the section of the desk that best fits the general topic of your question (see the navigation column to the right).
  • Post your question to only one section, providing a short header that gives the topic of your question.
  • Type '~~~~' (that is, four tilde characters) at the end – this signs and dates your contribution so we know who wrote what and when.
  • Don't post personal contact information – it will be removed. Any answers will be provided here.
  • Please be as specific as possible, and include all relevant context – the usefulness of answers may depend on the context.
  • Note:
    • We don't answer (and may remove) questions that require medical diagnosis or legal advice.
    • We don't answer requests for opinions, predictions or debate.
    • We don't do your homework for you, though we'll help you past the stuck point.
    • We don't conduct original research or provide a free source of ideas, but we'll help you find information you need.



How do I answer a question?

Main page: Wikipedia:Reference desk/Guidelines

  • The best answers address the question directly, and back up facts with wikilinks and links to sources. Do not edit others' comments and do not give any medical or legal advice.
See also:


December 9

[edit]

If the Mersenne number 2^p-1 is prime, then must it be the smallest Mersenne prime == 1 mod p?

[edit]

If the Mersenne number 2^p-1 is prime, then must it be the smallest Mersenne prime == 1 mod p? (i.e. there is no prime q < p such that 2^q-1 is also a Mersenne prime == 1 mod p) If p is prime (no matter 2^p-1 is prime or not), 2^p-1 is always == 1 mod p. However, there are primes p such that there is a prime q < p such that 2^q-1 is also a Mersenne prime == 1 mod p:

but for these primes p, 2^p-1 is not prime, and my question is: Is there a prime p such that 2^p-1 is a prime and there is a prime q < p such that 2^q-1 is also a Mersenne prime == 1 mod p?

  • If 2^11-1 is prime, then this is true, since 2^11-1 is == 1 mod 31 and 2^31-1 is prime, but 2^11-1 is not prime
  • If 2^23-1 or 2^67-1 is prime, then this is true, since 2^23-1 and 2^67-1 are == 1 mod 89 and 2^89-1 is prime, but 2^23-1 and 2^67-1 are not primes
  • If 2^29-1 or 2^43-1 or 2^71-1 or 2^113-1 is prime, then this is true, since 2^29-1 and 2^43-1 and 2^71-1 and 2^113-1 are == 1 mod 127 and 2^127-1 is prime, but 2^29-1 and 2^43-1 and 2^71-1 and 2^113-1 are not primes
  • If 2^191-1 or 2^571-1 or 2^761-1 or 2^1901-1 is prime, then this is true, since 2^191-1 and 2^571-1 and 2^761-1 and 2^1901-1 are == 1 mod 2281 and 2^2281-1 is prime, but 2^191-1 and 2^571-1 and 2^761-1 and 2^1901-1 are not primes
  • If 2^1609-1 is prime, then this is true, since 2^1609-1 is == 1 mod 3217 and 2^3217-1 is prime, but 2^1609-1 is not prime

Another question: For any prime p, is there always a Mersenne prime == 1 mod p? 220.132.216.52 (talk) 19:03, 9 December 2024 (UTC)[reply]

Neither question is easy. For the first, relations would imply that the integer 2 is not a primitive root mod p, and that its order divides for the prime q. This is a sufficiently infrequent occurrence that it seems likely that all Mersenne numbers could be ruled out statistically, but not enough is known about their distribution. For the second, it is not even known if there are infinitely many Mersenne primes. Tito Omburo (talk) 19:23, 9 December 2024 (UTC)[reply]
I found that: 2^9689-1 is the smallest Mersenne prime == 1 mod 29, 2^44497-1 is the smallest Mersenne prime == 1 mod 37, 2^756839-1 is the smallest Mersenne prime == 1 mod 47, 2^57885161-1 is the smallest Mersenne prime == 1 mod 59, 2^4423-1 is the smallest Mersenne prime == 1 mod 67, 2^9941-1 is the smallest Mersenne prime == 1 mod 71, 2^3217-1 is the smallest Mersenne prime == 1 mod 97, 2^21701-1 is the smallest Mersenne prime == 1 mod 101, and none of the 52 known Mersenne primes are == 1 mod these primes p < 1024: 79, 83, 103, 173, 193, 197, 199, 227, 239, 277, 307, 313, 317, 349, 359, 367, 373, 383, 389, 409, 419, 431, 443, 461, 463, 467, 479, 487, 503, 509, 523, 547, 563, 587, 599, 613, 647, 653, 659, 661, 677, 709, 727, 733, 739, 743, 751, 757, 769, 773, 797, 809, 821, 823, 827, 829, 839, 853, 857, 859, 863, 887, 907, 911, 919, 929, 937, 941, 947, 971, 977, 983, 991, 1013, 1019, 1021 220.132.216.52 (talk) 20:51, 9 December 2024 (UTC)[reply]
Also,
but none of these primes p has 2^p-1 is known to be prime, the status of 2^(2^89-1)-1 and 2^(2^107-1)-1 are still unknown (see double Mersenne number), but if at least one of them is prime, then will disprove this conjecture (none of the 52 known Mersenne primes are == 1 mod 2^61-1 or 2^127-1), I think that this conjecture may be as hard as the New Mersenne conjecture. 220.132.216.52 (talk) 20:55, 9 December 2024 (UTC)[reply]
Also, for the primes p < 10000, there is a prime q < p such that 2^q-1 is also a Mersenne prime == 1 mod p only for p = 73, 151, 257, 331, 337, 353, 397, 683, 1321, 1613, 2113, 2731, 4289, 4561, 5113, 5419, 6361, 8191, 9649 (this sequence is not in OEIS), however, none of these primes p have 2^p-1 prime. 220.132.216.52 (talk) 02:23, 10 December 2024 (UTC)[reply]

December 10

[edit]

More on the above conjecture

[edit]

Above I posed:

Conjecture. Every prime number can be written in one of the three forms and

If true, it implies no natural prime is a prime in the ring .

The absolute-value bars are not necessary. A number that can be written in the form is also expressible in the form

It turns out (experimentally; no proof) that a number that can be written in two of these forms can also be written in the third form. The conjecture is not strongly related to the concept of primality, as can be seen in this reformulation:

Conjecture. A natural number that cannot be written in any one of the three forms and is composite.

The first few numbers that cannot be written in any one of these three forms are

They are indeed all composite, but why this should be so is a mystery to me. What do and which appear later in the list, have in common? I see no pattern.

It seems furthermore that the primorials, starting with make the list. (Checked up to )  --Lambiam 19:23, 10 December 2024 (UTC)[reply]

Quick note, for those like me who are curious how numbers of the form can be written into a form of , note that , and so . GalacticShoe (talk) 02:20, 11 December 2024 (UTC)[reply]
A prime is expressible as the sum of two squares if and only if it is congruent to , as per Fermat's theorem on sums of two squares. A prime is expressible of the form if and only if it is congruent to , as per OEIS:A002479. And a prime is expressible of the form if and only if it is congruent to , as per OEIS:A035251. Between these congruences, all primes are covered. GalacticShoe (talk) 05:59, 11 December 2024 (UTC)[reply]
More generally, a number is not expressible as:
  1. if it has a prime factor congruent to that is raised to an odd power (equivalently, .)
  2. if it has a prime factor congruent to that is raised to an odd power
  3. if it has a prime factor congruent to that is raised to an odd power
It is easy to see why expressibility as any two of these forms leads to the third form holding, and also we can see why it's difficult to see a pattern in numbers that are expressible in none of these forms, in particular we get somewhat-convoluted requirements on exponents of primes in the factorization satisfying congruences modulo 8. GalacticShoe (talk) 06:17, 11 December 2024 (UTC)[reply]
Thanks. Is any of this covered in some Wikipedia article?  --Lambiam 10:06, 11 December 2024 (UTC)[reply]
All primes? 2 is not covered! 176.0.133.82 (talk) 08:00, 17 December 2024 (UTC)[reply]
can be written in all three forms:  --Lambiam 09:38, 17 December 2024 (UTC)[reply]
I don't say it's not covered by the conjecture. I say it's not covered by the discussed classes of remainders. 176.0.133.82 (talk) 14:54, 17 December 2024 (UTC)[reply]
Odd prime, my bad. GalacticShoe (talk) 16:38, 17 December 2024 (UTC)[reply]

Assume p is 3 mod 4. Suppose that (2|p)=1. Then where . Because the cyclotomic ideal has norm and is stable under the Galois action it is generated by a single element , of norm .

If (2|p)=-1, then the relevant ideal is stable under and so is generated by , of norm . Tito Omburo (talk) 14:43, 11 December 2024 (UTC)[reply]

December 11

[edit]

Unique normal ultrafilter

[edit]

So I'm supposed to know the answer to this, I suppose, but I don't seem to :-)

"Everyone knows" that, in , Gödel's constructible universe relative to an ultrafilter on some measurable cardinal , there is only a single normal ultrafilter, namely itself. See for example John R. Steel's monograph here, at Theorem 1.7.

So I guess that must mean that the product measure , meaning you fix some identification between and and then say a set has measure 1 if measure 1 many of its vertical sections have measure 1, must not be normal. (Unless it's somehow just equal to but I don't think it is.)

But is there some direct way to see that? Say, a continuous function with such that the set of fixed points of is not in the ultrafilter no singleton has a preimage under that's in the ultrafilter? I haven't been able to come up with it. --Trovatore (talk) 06:01, 11 December 2024 (UTC)[reply]



December 15

[edit]

What is the cause of this paradox?

[edit]

I recently completed a calculus term, in which one of the last units involving how much one aspect of an object was changing in relation to time at a certain point, given the rate of change of another aspect. Many specific questions could be analyzed as a right triangle with one leg (the x) remaining constant and the other leg (the y) growing at a specified rate. When it came time to solve for the value of the dz/dt (the rate of the hypotenuse’s growth with respect to time) at a certain point, it ended up as less than the provided dy/dt. Here’s an illustration:

The x is the distance from me to a tower. This remains constant.

The y is the distance from the tower to a flying bird.

The dy/dt is the speed at which the bird is flying from the tower.

The z is my distance from the bird.

In this illustration, the distance between me and the bird is increasing at a slower rate than the speed at which the bird itself is flying. What is the cause of this paradox? Primal Groudon (talk) 19:43, 15 December 2024 (UTC)[reply]

I do not see any paradox here. Ruslik_Zero 20:30, 15 December 2024 (UTC)[reply]
If the bird is between you and the tower (0 ≤ y < x), the distance between you and the bird is even decreasing: dz/dt < 0. By the time it flies right overhead (y = x), the distance is momentarily stationary: dz/dt = 0. After that, it increases: dz/dt > 0. This rate of increase will asymptotically approach dy/dt from below as the bird flies off into an infinite distance.  --Lambiam 00:34, 16 December 2024 (UTC)[reply]
I think the issue here is that even though the rate of change of z is less than the rate of change of y, z never actually becomes less than y. You can see this graphically, for example, by comparing the graphs of y=x and y=√(x2+1). The second graph is always above the first graph, but the slope of the first graph is x/√(x2+1), which is always less than 1, the slope of the first graph. But this is typical behavior when a graph has an asymptote. As a simpler example, the slope of 1/x is negative, but the value never goes below 0 (at least for x>0). Similarly, the slope of x+1/x is always less than 1, but the value of x+1/x is always greater than x (again, for x>0). The graph of y=√(x2+1) is one branch of a hyperbola having y=x as an asymptote, and this looks very much like the x>0 part of y=x+1/x. In general the difference in rates of change can imply that that two quantities get closer and closer to each other, but this does not mean they ever become equal. This phenomenon is, perhaps, counterintuitive for many people, but the math says it can happen anyway. I don't know if this rises to the level of a paradox, but I can see that it might be concerning for some. --RDBury (talk) 09:39, 16 December 2024 (UTC)[reply]
For x > 0, the graph of y=√(x2+1) looks even more like that of y=x+1/(2x). For example, when x = 5, √(x2+1) = 26 ≈ 5.09902 is approximated much more closely by 5.1 than by 5.2.  --Lambiam 18:35, 16 December 2024 (UTC)[reply]



December 19

[edit]

Who is the following unknown?

[edit]

When asked "WHO IS YOUR X?" (X still being unknown to me but is known to the respondents), here are the answers I get:

A answers: "A"
B answers: "C"
C answers: "C"
D answers: "F"
E answers: "F"
F answers: "F"

To sum up, the special phenomenon here is that, everybody has their own X (usually), and if any respondent points at another respondent as the first respondent's X, then the other respondent must point at themself as their X.

I wonder who the unknown X may be, when I only know that X is a natural example from everyday life. I thought about a couple of examples, but none of them are satisfactory, as follows:

X is the leader of one's political party, or X is one's mayor, and the like, but all of these examples attribute some kind of leadership or superiority to X, whereas I'm not interested in this kind of solution - involving any superiority of X.

Here is a second solution I thought about: X is the first (or last) person born in the year/month the respondent was born, and the like. But this solution involves some kind of order (in which there is a "first person" and a "last person"), whereas I'm not interested in this kind of solution - involving any order.

Btw, I've published this question also at the Miscellaneous desk, because this question is about everyday life, but now I decide to publish this question also here, because it's indirectly related to a well known topic in Math. 79.177.151.182 (talk) 13:27, 19 December 2024 (UTC)[reply]

Head of household comes to mind as a fairly natural one. The colours then correspond to different households which can be just one person. One objection is that "head of household" is a fairy traditional concept. With marriage equality now being the norm it's perhaps outdated. --2A04:4A43:909F:F9FF:397E:BBF9:E80B:CB36 (talk) 15:11, 19 December 2024 (UTC)[reply]
I have already referred to this kind of solution, in the example of "my mayor", see above why this solution is not satisfactory. 79.177.151.182 (talk) 15:31, 19 December 2024 (UTC)[reply]

The question has been resolved at the Miscellaneous reference desk.

Resolved

79.177.151.182 (talk) 15:48, 19 December 2024 (UTC)[reply]

X may well be 'the oldest living person of your ancestry'. --CiaPan (talk) 20:46, 19 December 2024 (UTC)[reply]

Resolved or not, let's try to analyze this mathematically. Given is some set and some function For the example, with
Knowing that "everybody has their own X (usually)", we can normalize the unusual situation that function might not be total in two ways. The first is to restrict the set to the domain of that is, the set of elements on which is defined. This is possible because of the condition that implies so this does not introduce an undue limitation of the range of The second approach is to postulate that whenever might otherwise be undefined. Which of these two approaches is chosen makes no essential difference.
Let be the range of , given by:
Clearly, if we have We know, conversely, that implies
Let us also consider the inverse image of , given by:
Suppose that This means that there exists some which in turns means that But then we know that Combining this, we have,
The inverse-image function restricted to to which we assign the typing
now induces a partitioning of into non-empty, mutually disjoint subsets, which means they are the classes of an equivalence relation. Each class has its own unique representative, which is the single element of the class that is also a member of . The equivalence relation can be expressed formally by
and the representatives are the fixed points of
Applying this to the original example, and the equivalence classes are:
  • with representative
  • with representative and
  • with representative
Conversely, any partitioning of a set defines an equivalence relation; together with the selection of a representative for each equivalence class, this gives an instance of the situation defined in the question.  --Lambiam 20:47, 19 December 2024 (UTC)[reply]
FWIW, the number of such objects on a set of size n is given by OEISA000248, and that page has a number of other combinatorial interpretations. If you ignore the selection of a representative for each class, you get the Bell numbers. --RDBury (talk) 00:35, 21 December 2024 (UTC)[reply]

December 20

[edit]

Give a base b and two base b digits x and z, must there be a base b digits y such that the 3-digit number xyz in base b is prime?

[edit]

Give a base b and two base b digits x and z (x is not 0, z is coprime to b), must there be a base b digits y such that the 3-digit number xyz in base b is prime? 1.165.207.39 (talk) 02:10, 20 December 2024 (UTC)[reply]

In base 5, is composite for all base-5 Y. GalacticShoe (talk) 03:39, 20 December 2024 (UTC)[reply]
also offers a counterexample. While there are many counterexamples for most odd bases, I did not find any for even bases.  --Lambiam 09:58, 20 December 2024 (UTC)[reply]


December 23

[edit]

Is it possible to make Twisted Edwards curve birationally equivalent to twisted weirestrass curves ?

[edit]

Is there an equation fo converting a twisted Edwards curve into a tiwsted weierstrass form ? 2A01:E0A:401:A7C0:6D06:298B:1495:F479 (talk) 04:12, 23 December 2024 (UTC)[reply]